Sysop: | Amessyroom |
---|---|
Location: | Fayetteville, NC |
Users: | 23 |
Nodes: | 6 (0 / 6) |
Uptime: | 50:05:30 |
Calls: | 583 |
Files: | 1,138 |
Messages: | 111,306 |
It is claimed that a topology O on a space M is the simplest structure
which affords a notion of continuity. Two questions:
1] is there a proof of this?
It is claimed that a topology O on a space M is the simplest structure
which affords a notion of continuity. Two questions:
1] is there a proof of this?
2] what other structures on spaces (considered as sets of points) give notions of continuity?
On 23/08/2025 22:15, Peter Fairbrother wrote:
It is claimed that a topology O on a space M is the simplest structure
which affords a notion of continuity. Two questions:
No, see e.g. Wikipedia: topology provides the *most general*
setting to define limits and continuous of a function. <https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Continuous_function>
OTOH, arguably, the *simplest* such setting is based on the
epsilon-delta definitions over the real numbers: simplest as
some geometric intuition about points on the real line should
be enough to get the idea.
1] is there a proof of this?
Simplicity is subjective, but yes about generality: indeed,
based on the definitions involved, it is of course possible to
*prove* that a theory is more general than another: as in, the
former can "interpret" the latter, but not the other way round.
-Julio
It is claimed that a topology O on a space M is the simplest structure which affords a notion of
continuity. Two questions:
1] is there a proof of this?
2] what other structures on spaces (considered as sets of points) give notions of continuity?
On 23/08/2025 21:15, Peter Fairbrother wrote:
It is claimed that a topology O on a space M is the simplest structure which
affords a notion of
continuity. Two questions:
1] is there a proof of this?
I doubt it. (It's not really a mathematical statement, more the sort of motivational remark an
author might make when introducing a student to the subject.)
2] what other structures on spaces (considered as sets of points) give notions
of continuity?
Well, there are metric spaces and uniform spaces. Both of those are extensively
studied, and give
rise in a natural way to an underlying topological space. (That's not to suggest there aren't other
ways of approaching continuity - those examples were just what came to mind.)
Mike.
Le 28/08/2025 |a 19:11, Mike Terry a |-crit :
On 23/08/2025 21:15, Peter Fairbrother wrote:
It is claimed that a topology O on a space M is the simplest
structure which affords a notion of continuity. Two questions:
1] is there a proof of this?
I doubt it. (It's not really a mathematical statement, more the sort
of motivational remark an author might make when introducing a student
to the subject.)
2] what other structures on spaces (considered as sets of points)
give notions of continuity?
Well, there are metric spaces and uniform spaces. Both of those are
extensively studied, and give rise in a natural way to an underlying
topological space. (That's not to suggest there aren't other ways of
approaching continuity - those examples were just what came to mind.)
Mike.
I would say, nevertheless, that the topological definition is simpler
that the epsilon-delta one, as the first one is more general (a metric implies a topology not the other way around). Another definition, not
taught as much, is the definition in term of filters (as in Bourbaki's
books) which can be seen as even more general as the topological
definition.
On 08/28/2025 12:50 PM, Python wrote:
Le 28/08/2025 |a 19:11, Mike Terry a |-crit :
On 23/08/2025 21:15, Peter Fairbrother wrote:
It is claimed that a topology O on a space M is the simplest
structure which affords a notion of continuity. Two questions:
1] is there a proof of this?
I doubt it. (It's not really a mathematical statement, more the sort
of motivational remark an author might make when introducing a student
to the subject.)
2] what other structures on spaces (considered as sets of points)
give notions of continuity?
Well, there are metric spaces and uniform spaces. Both of those are
extensively studied, and give rise in a natural way to an underlying
topological space. (That's not to suggest there aren't other ways of
approaching continuity - those examples were just what came to mind.)
Mike.
I would say, nevertheless, that the topological definition is simpler
that the epsilon-delta one, as the first one is more general (a metric
implies a topology not the other way around). Another definition, not
taught as much, is the definition in term of filters (as in Bourbaki's
books) which can be seen as even more general as the topological
definition.
Sounds like somebody who says Dedekind cuts are field-reals, when
everybody knows that equivalence classes of sequences that are
Cauchy, are field-reals, and that if there are Dedekind cuts of
those, it's as of those, since the rationals are not gapless.
It's like somebody who says the initial ordinal assignment is the
cardinal, when the cardinal is the equivalence class of all those.
It's like somebody who doesn't know that continuous functions
are continuous functions whether or not they're over continuous
domains.
On 08/30/2025 03:51 AM, Ross Finlayson wrote:
On 08/28/2025 12:50 PM, Python wrote:
Le 28/08/2025 |a 19:11, Mike Terry a |-crit :
On 23/08/2025 21:15, Peter Fairbrother wrote:
It is claimed that a topology O on a space M is the simplest
structure which affords a notion of continuity. Two questions:
1] is there a proof of this?
I doubt it. (It's not really a mathematical statement, more the sort
of motivational remark an author might make when introducing a student >>>> to the subject.)
2] what other structures on spaces (considered as sets of points)
give notions of continuity?
Well, there are metric spaces and uniform spaces. Both of those are
extensively studied, and give rise in a natural way to an underlying
topological space. (That's not to suggest there aren't other ways of
approaching continuity - those examples were just what came to mind.)
Mike.
I would say, nevertheless, that the topological definition is simpler
that the epsilon-delta one, as the first one is more general (a metric
implies a topology not the other way around). Another definition, not
taught as much, is the definition in term of filters (as in Bourbaki's
books) which can be seen as even more general as the topological
definition.
Sounds like somebody who says Dedekind cuts are field-reals, when
everybody knows that equivalence classes of sequences that are
Cauchy, are field-reals, and that if there are Dedekind cuts of
those, it's as of those, since the rationals are not gapless.
It's like somebody who says the initial ordinal assignment is the
cardinal, when the cardinal is the equivalence class of all those.
It's like somebody who doesn't know that continuous functions
are continuous functions whether or not they're over continuous
domains.
It sort of reminds of, "differential geometry". "To define our
immersions and submersions, so that a bunch of numerical methods
of Coates and Gregory apply, define 'function' as like a classical
function yet, not only having no asymptote in our coordinate
setting, also its tangent vector normal having no asymptote,
essentially eliminating values of infinity already, zero also".
And it's like, "maybe so, if every time you write 'f' and 'g'
for functions they're written 'f_DG' and 'g_DG' for this
subfield of 'differential geometry's'".
The widespread use of "almost all" or "almost everywhere" is
another sort of example, sometimes innocuous, others erroneous.
It's like 'what's convergence' and "well it results series
that are Cauchy" and "how exactly is that...", "any number of
convergence tests that aren't wrong". Ah, .... That though
is more about that there are inductive results that aren't
necessarily true "in the limit" as when things complete in
the limit.
The idea of a topology, that's also its own initial and final
topology, as with regards to spaces and points therein, and
whatever divides or adds those, sort of makes topology speak
to continuity instead of vice versa.
It sort of makes at least enough sense when "well it's sort
of interchangeable with the concept of points 'in' a line and
points 'on' a line, those being two different things".